Toleration Is Not Enough to Sustain a Liberal Order
Buddhist philosophy's emphasis on feeling 'sympathetic joy' for different life choices will make us love a liberal society with its resplendent differences
Dear Readers:
It is an open question whether a liberal polity can survive our age of hyper political polarization when we would prefer that our loved ones marry someone of a different religion than an opposing political party. Partisans of liberalism believe that the solution to this problem is to inculcate an affection for liberal institutions by emphasizing the unprecedented peace and prosperity these institutions have delivered. Won’t a clear understanding of what’s at stake move people to set aside their disagreements, tolerate each other’s differences, and back away from the growing talk of “civil war”?
But what if that is not enough? What if liberalism requires not merely an intellectual appreciation for liberal institutions but a liberal ethos, a liberal temperament? This is a question that an upcoming review of John Cherniss’ book Liberalism in Dark Times: The Liberal Ethos in the Twentieth Century, will tackle.
Today, however, Aaron Ross Powell, the charming host of ReImagining Liberty, a podcast of The UnPopulist, and a practicing Buddhist, consults his philosophical tradition to offer a statement of what such a temperament would look like. He suggests that it requires not a mere toleration of the different life choices of individuals but taking a “celebratory joy” in them.
He does not seek to convince people through logic-chopping rigor exactly how this would work. What his essay does attempt to do is reset the social default so that instead of beginning with rejecting life choices different from ours till they prove of some value to us, we do the opposite, we seek to accept these choices unless we see some harm in them. This approach won’t make fundamental conflicts of value disappear, but it’ll allow us to sidestep at least some of them.
It is an intriguing new way to think about the limits of liberal toleration.
If you are looking for a thought-provoking Saturday read, this is it.
Shikha Dalmia
One way to defend liberal institutions is to argue that they are value neutral. Thus a liberal government protects the persons and property of its citizens, but doesn’t coerce them into a particular conception of the good life. Under a liberal regime, you can be a teetotaler or a lush, a Christian or a Muslim, a hedonist or an aesthetic. Thus liberalism is desirable, in part, because it supports robust pluralism. We needn’t fight with one another about how to live, because some narrow range of society’s diverse preferences won’t be codified into law.
And while any attempt to move the political regime of a liberal society away from that core commitment to law’s value neutrality should be fought tooth and nail, it’s not the case that legal neutrality doesn’t have the effect of making some values and preferences more likely to find success in the resulting society. How our individual values and preferences interact with diverse people—and their diverse values and preferences—can impact how happy we’ll be, and how much of our lives are spent enjoying a liberal society versus resenting it.
Because most of us want to be happy—we want ours to be lives of flourishing—the fact that some values and beliefs are more conducive to that than others within a liberal society means that political liberalism, in the value-neutral sense, nonetheless rewards, and so encourages, certain traits of character. Fortunately, the very traits that liberalism rewards are those that make political liberalism more robust—and the traits that make liberalism more robust are those of admirable people more likely to lead ethical and flourishing lives. Thus, unless it’s short circuited by political intervention or toxic ideologies, liberalism constructs a positive feedback loop, where good people are more likely to be liberal people, and liberal people are more likely to be good people.
Many traits fall into what I call these “liberal virtues,” but here I want to focus on goodwill and sympathetic joy. I’m using these terms in an Eastern philosophy sense, specifically Buddhist philosophy. Goodwill, as the scholar Ṭhānissaro Bhikkhu puts it, is “a wish for true happiness, both for yourself and for others. Because the highest level of true happiness comes from within, your true happiness need not conflict with that of anyone else. Thus goodwill can be extended to all beings without contradiction or hypocrisy.” Within that, then, sympathetic joy is simply “what grows out of goodwill when you see happiness: You want that happiness to continue.” Another way to think about it is “finding joy in the happiness and success of others.”
We need to be careful not to confuse goodwill or sympathetic joy with “loving everyone” or “never being critical of another’s behavior.” Even if either were possible, neither would be desirable, or even rational. We can’t love everyone the way we love our family and friends, but we can wish that everyone find happiness, even if we personally want nothing to do with them. Goodwill and sympathetic joy can be universal in a way that love cannot.
“Happiness” in “finding joy in the happiness and success of others” speaks to happiness from their perspective, not necessarily our own. It is subjective and pluralistic. What makes me happy isn’t necessarily what would make you happy, but we can both recognize that each other’s happiness is genuine. This can be true even if what makes another happy we find personally distasteful. (A critical point, for example, in the anti-transgender moral panic on the right.)
“Success” is likewise a personal measure. Our culture tends to define success by our bank balance, fame, or, among adherents of Ayn Rand, our productivity. (For a debunking of why the last is a faulty metric for happiness, go here.) But holding success to those narrow confines is obviously incorrect. Rather, we should think of success as, roughly, having the life you want, or having the life that makes you happy. If that’s being a titan of industry, so be it. But the monk living in the woods and never earning a dime, or the “underemployed” person making enough to afford a simple lifestyle they find contentment with, is equally successful.
Of course, we can be mistaken about our own happiness, or believe we’re successful when we’re not, because we can be making choices that are harmful or that we’ll later profoundly regret. But our default should be to trust people’s subjective judgment, because they know more about their own goals and satisfaction than we do. And we should be very careful about elevating our personal preferences to universal truths about human flourishing. It can certainly be the case that what a person takes to make them happy is, in fact, actually harmful, even violently so, to others.
Buddhist philosophy is clear that happiness can only come about through skillful intentions, meaning not motivated by “ill will, cruelty, resentment.” Knowing with certainty where to draw that line when it comes to another’s subjective happiness—or “happiness”—is impossible. But that it’s impossible doesn’t mean we need to give up on the distinction, or let ourselves fall into the trap of thinking only that which aligns with our own subjective conceptions of happiness is true and worthy. A liberal society is inevitably messy, but messiness is not nihilism. And cultivating traits of goodwill and sympathetic joy will make us better able to recognize genuinely unskillful intentions, while cultivating or giving into ill-will and resentment will make us far less likely to recognize and appreciate others’ skillful happiness.
This is, in fact, one path to illiberalism. It comes from failing to recognize happiness and success in alternative ways of living, and so insisting both must conform to a narrow range. From there, the illiberal concludes that the problem with freedom is it enables and encourages people to pursue success and happiness outside of “traditional” ways. Illiberals see any happiness and success that doesn’t align with their preferences as false, inauthentic, mistaken or corrupt. Thus, to return to the prior example, transgender people aren’t actually happy in their gender identity, but are instead mentally ill and secretly miserable. Illiberals on the left can make a similar move, assuming that people who freely choose “traditionally” conservative lifestyles, or hold to restrictive religious faiths or opt to raise children instead of seeking careers, aren’t genuinely happy and aren’t meaningfully successful.
Goodwill and sympathetic joy are clearly virtues. A person who isn’t resentful of others’ happiness has a better character than a person who is. And a person who in fact finds joy in others’ happiness takes that good character a step further. We admire (or should admire) such large-hearted people, and strive to cultivate this feeling in ourselves.
But what does this have to do with liberalism?
A society permeated more thoroughly with the virtues of goodwill and sympathetic joy is likely to better maintain political liberalism than one grounded in mere toleration. Illiberalism comes about in part because people have reached a limit of how much difference they’ll tolerate, and they turn against liberty, and toward the state, to put a stop to lifestyle choices they dislike. If illiberalism takes strength from intolerance, then cultivating virtues that go beyond tolerance into sympathetic joy strengthens liberalism’s defenses. And if we’ve come to view the happiness of others as a key component of our own happiness, then restricting their freedom to pursue success as they define it will be seen as not only making them worse off, but ourselves as well. It’ll cause us pain, not give us joy, to do so.
Virtues are cultivated, and the environment we’re in can make it easier or harder to do so. The good news is that in a liberal society, there is an inherent incentive to develop these liberal virtues. Liberalism necessarily entails that we will be surrounded by people different from us, pursuing success in ways not our own, and finding happiness in places we don’t. Living in a liberal society will be quite miserable if we constantly resent different kinds of happiness and self-expression and harbor ill-will for those experiencing and embracing them. As Tibetan scholar Traleg Kyabgon puts it, “Feelings such as resentment and bitterness gradually make us weak, frustrated, and unhappy, rather than having any impact on the person toward whom we direct these emotions.” On the other hand, living in a liberal society will become not just tolerable, but a genuine delight, if we possess the virtue of sympathetic joy. Thus as liberal citizens, these virtues are a means to great life satisfaction, which we all should want and strive for.
This feedback loop, far from being value neutral, is one of liberalism’s great strengths. But to take advantage of it, we need to recognize it, and push back against the illiberal desire to resent happiness in difference and diversity. We should avoid the ideology of hang-ups, have little respect for religions that ask us to become worse people and accept tolerance as only a second-best alternative to a fuller internalizing of liberal virtues.
© The UnPopulist 2023
Follow The UnPopulist on: X, Threads, YouTube, TikTok, Facebook, Instagram, and Bluesky.
This “pre-political sentiment” harmonizes beautifully with David French’s recent take on an insight of Jimmy Carter:
In “The Wisdom and Prophecy of Jimmy Carter’s ‘Malaise’ Speech”, columnist David French opines that:
“Carter’s central insight was that even if the country’s political branches could deliver peace and prosperity, they could not deliver community and belonging. Our nation depends on pre-political commitments to each other, and in the absence of those pre-political commitments, the American experiment is ultimately in jeopardy.”
Let sympathetic joy be the liberal order’s little engine that could.
While I like the idea of cultivating joy in other people's version of the good life when it differs from mine, I think requiring it as part of liberalism actually weakens liberalism.
To me the important part of liberalism is that it is completely opposed to our intuition, our feelings, our baser human nature. For example, I should support free speech for Nazis, even if I think their speech is harmful, terrible, and an affront. This piece seems to argue that I should be supporting free speech for Nazis because I should be happy for them that they are pursuing their life goals according to their own metric. That weakens the idea of rights even for people I hate.
To put this another way, some human beings are always going to hate other human beings, sometimes for good reason. I would rather have a rule that says "rights even for those you hate" rather than a rule that says "don't hate anyone". "Rights even for those you hate" seems to align much better with the realities of human nature. I prefer that than trying to tell myself that all pursuits of happiness are equally likely to turn out well.
This discussion kind of reminds me of the tendency on the left to say that Elon Musk is dumb and only wealthy because of his father. In reality, Elon Musk can simultaneously be doing stupid things, be a terrible person, and also be smart and earned some of the wealth through his own actions. It seems like the left wants to simplify in this case, but it doesn't need to. Smart people can do dumb stuff. Wealthy people can have ill-gotten and well-gotten gains. We don't need to simplify, and this kind of simplification causes us to be wrong about the world in ways that will cause us to err in future predictions.
I really want to keep the rule "rights even for those you hate". If we want to work on not hating people, that's great, but I definitely do not want to weaken the principle by turning it into "rights for everyone because I should appreciate their pursuit of happiness even if it is awful". I think that's beyond the reach of most, and honestly I'm not sure it is desirable. I think it's good for me not to like a Nazi's pursuit of happiness.